World Library  
Flag as Inappropriate
Email this Article

Μ-recursive function

Article Id: WHEBN0000026469
Reproduction Date:

Title: Μ-recursive function  
Author: World Heritage Encyclopedia
Language: English
Subject: Computable function, Computable number, Primitive recursive function, Church–Turing thesis, LOOP (programming language)
Collection:
Publisher: World Heritage Encyclopedia
Publication
Date:
 

Μ-recursive function

In mathematical logic and computer science, the μ-recursive functions are a class of partial functions from natural numbers to natural numbers that are "computable" in an intuitive sense. In fact, in computability theory it is shown that the μ-recursive functions are precisely the functions that can be computed by Turing machines. The μ-recursive functions are closely related to primitive recursive functions, and their inductive definition (below) builds upon that of the primitive recursive functions. However, not every μ-recursive function is a primitive recursive function—the most famous example is the Ackermann function.

Other equivalent classes of functions are the λ-recursive functions and the functions that can be computed by Markov algorithms.

The set of all recursive functions is known as R in computational complexity theory.

Definition

The μ-recursive functions (or partial μ-recursive functions) are partial functions that take finite tuples of natural numbers and return a single natural number. They are the smallest class of partial functions that includes the initial functions and is closed under composition, primitive recursion, and the μ operator.

The smallest class of functions including the initial functions and closed under composition and primitive recursion (i.e. without minimisation) is the class of primitive recursive functions. While all primitive recursive functions are total, this is not true of partial recursive functions; for example, the minimisation of the successor function is undefined. The primitive recursive functions are a subset of the total recursive functions, which are a subset of the partial recursive functions. For example, the Ackermann function can be proven to be total recursive, but not primitive.

Initial or "basic" functions: (In the following the subscripting is per Kleene (1952) p. 219. For more about some of the various symbolisms found in the literature see Symbolism below.)

  1. Constant function: For each natural number n\, and every k\,:
    f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) = n\,.
    Alternative definitions use compositions of the successor function and use a zero function, that always returns zero, in place of the constant function.
  2. Successor function S:
    S(x) \stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{=} f(x) = x + 1\,
  3. Projection function P_i^k (also called the Identity function I_i^k): For all natural numbers i, k\, such that 1 \le i \le k:
    P_i^k \stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{=} f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) = x_i.

Operators:

  1. Composition operator \circ\, (also called the substitution operator): Given an m-ary function h(x_1,\ldots,x_m)\, and m k-ary functions g_1(x_1,\ldots,x_k),\ldots,g_m(x_1,\ldots, x_k):
    h \circ (g_1, \ldots, g_m) \stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{=} f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) = h(g_1(x_1,\ldots,x_k),\ldots,g_m(x_1,\ldots,x_k))\,.
  2. Primitive recursion operator \rho\,: Given the k-ary function g(x_1,\ldots,x_k)\, and k+2 -ary function h(y,z,x_1,\ldots,x_k)\,:
    \begin{align} \rho(g, h) &\stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{=} f(y, x_1,\ldots, x_k) \quad {\rm where} \\ f(0,x_1,\ldots,x_k) &= g(x_1,\ldots,x_k) \\ f(y+1,x_1,\ldots,x_k) &= h(y,f(y,x_1,\ldots,x_k),x_1,\ldots,x_k)\,\end{align}.
  3. Minimisation operator \mu\,: Given a (k+1)-ary total function f(y, x_1, \ldots, x_k)\,:
    \begin{align} \mu(f)(x_1, \ldots, x_k) = z \stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{\iff}\ f(z, x_1, \ldots, x_k)&=0\quad \text{and}\\ f(i, x_1, \ldots, x_k)&>0 \quad \text{for}\ i=0, \ldots, z-1. \end{align}
    Intuitively, minimisation seeks—beginning the search from 0 and proceeding upwards—the smallest argument that causes the function to return zero; if there is no such argument, the search never terminates.

The strong equality operator \simeq can be used to compare partial μ-recursive functions. This is defined for all partial functions f and g so that

f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) \simeq g(x_1,\ldots,x_l)

holds if and only if for any choice of arguments either both functions are defined and their values are equal or both functions are undefined.

Equivalence with other models of computability

In the equivalence of models of computability, a parallel is drawn between Turing machines that do not terminate for certain inputs and an undefined result for that input in the corresponding partial recursive function. The unbounded search operator is not definable by the rules of primitive recursion as those do not provide a mechanism for "infinite loops" (undefined values).

Normal form theorem

A normal form theorem due to Kleene says that for each k there are primitive recursive functions U(y)\! and T(y,e,x_1,\ldots,x_k)\! such that for any μ-recursive function f(x_1,\ldots,x_k)\! with k free variables there is an e such that

f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) \simeq U(\mu y\, T(y,e,x_1,\ldots,x_k)).

The number e is called an index or Gödel number for the function f. A consequence of this result is that any μ-recursive function can be defined using a single instance of the μ operator applied to a (total) primitive recursive function.

Minsky (1967) observes (as does Boolos-Burgess-Jeffrey (2002) pp. 94–95) that the U defined above is in essence the μ-recursive equivalent of the universal Turing machine:

To construct U is to write down the definition of a general-recursive function U(n, x) that correctly interprets the number n and computes the appropriate function of x. to construct U directly would involve essentially the same amount of effort, and essentially the same ideas, as we have invested in constructing the universal Turing machine. (italics in original, Minsky (1967) p. 189)

Symbolism

A number of different symbolisms are used in the literature. An advantage to using the symbolism is a derivation of a function by "nesting" of the operators one inside the other is easier to write in a compact form. In the following we will abbreviate the string of parameters x1, ..., xn as x:

  • Constant function: Kleene uses " Cqn(x) = q " and Boolos-Burgess-Jeffry (2002) (B-B-J) use the abbreviation " constn( x) = n ":
e.g. C137 ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = 13
e.g. const13 ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = 13
  • Successor function: Kleene uses x' and S for "Successor". As "successor" is considered to be primitive, most texts use the apostrophe as follows:
S(a) = a +1 =def a', where 1 =def 0', 2 =def 0 ' ', etc.
  • Identity function: Kleene (1952) uses " Uin " to indicate the identity function over the variables xi; B-B-J use the identity function idin over the variables x1 to xn:
Uin( x ) = idin( x ) = xi
e.g. U37 = id37 ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = t
  • Composition (Substitution) operator: Kleene uses a bold-face Snm (not to be confused with his S for "successor" ! ). The superscript "m" refers to the mth of function "fm", whereas the subscript "n" refers to the nth variable "xn":
If we are given h( x )= g( f1(x), ... , fm(x) )
h(x) = Smn(g, f1, ... , fm )
In a similar manner, but without the sub- and superscripts, B-B-J write:
h(x')= Cn[g, f1 ,..., fm](x)
  • Primitive Recursion: Kleene uses the symbol " Rn(base step, induction step) " where n indicates the number of variables, B-B-J use " Pr(base step, induction step)(x)". Given:
  • base step: h( 0, x )= f( x ), and
  • induction step: h( y+1, x ) = g( y, h(y, x),x )
Example: primitive recursion definition of a + b:
  • base step: f( 0, a ) = a = U11(a)
  • induction step: f( b' , a ) = ( f ( b, a ) )' = g( b, f( b, a), a ) = g( b, c, a ) = c' = S(U23( b, c, a )
R2 { U11(a), S [ (U23( b, c, a ) ] }
Pr{ U11(a), S[ (U23( b, c, a ) ] }

Example: Kleene gives an example of how to perform the recursive derivation of f(b, a) = b + a (notice reversal of variables a and b). He starting with 3 initial functions

  1. S(a) = a'
  2. U11(a) = a
  3. U23( b, c, a ) = c
  4. g(b, c, a) = S(U23( b, c, a )) = c'
  5. base step: h( 0, a ) = U11(a)
induction step: h( b', a ) = g( b, h( b, a ), a )

He arrives at:

a+b = R2[ U11, S13(S, U23) ]

Examples

See also

References

  • Stephen Kleene (1952) Introduction to Metamathematics. Walters-Noordhoff & North-Holland, with corrections (6th imprint 1971); Tenth impression 1991, ISBN 0-7204-2103-9.
  • Soare, R. Recursively enumerable sets and degrees. Springer-Verlag 1987.
  • Marvin L. Minsky (1967), Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines, Prentice-Hall, Inc. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.
On pages 210-215 Minsky shows how to create the μ-operator using the register machine model, thus demonstrating its equivalence to the general recursive functions.
  • John Burgess, Richard Jeffrey (2002), Computability and Logic: Fourth Edition, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK. Cf pp. 70–71.

External links

  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry
  • A compiler for transforming a recursive function into an equivalent Turing machine
This article was sourced from Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. World Heritage Encyclopedia content is assembled from numerous content providers, Open Access Publishing, and in compliance with The Fair Access to Science and Technology Research Act (FASTR), Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., Public Library of Science, The Encyclopedia of Life, Open Book Publishers (OBP), PubMed, U.S. National Library of Medicine, National Center for Biotechnology Information, U.S. National Library of Medicine, National Institutes of Health (NIH), U.S. Department of Health & Human Services, and USA.gov, which sources content from all federal, state, local, tribal, and territorial government publication portals (.gov, .mil, .edu). Funding for USA.gov and content contributors is made possible from the U.S. Congress, E-Government Act of 2002.
 
Crowd sourced content that is contributed to World Heritage Encyclopedia is peer reviewed and edited by our editorial staff to ensure quality scholarly research articles.
 
By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. World Heritage Encyclopedia™ is a registered trademark of the World Public Library Association, a non-profit organization.
 



Copyright © World Library Foundation. All rights reserved. eBooks from World Library are sponsored by the World Library Foundation,
a 501c(4) Member's Support Non-Profit Organization, and is NOT affiliated with any governmental agency or department.